Skip to content
Snippets Groups Projects
Unverified Commit 435fffec authored by rhatto's avatar rhatto
Browse files

Updates psicologia

parent 4da2fabb
Branches
No related tags found
No related merge requests found
......@@ -4,6 +4,10 @@
* Publisher: Routledge Classics.
* Year: 1950.
## References
* [Piaget's theory of cognitive development - Wikipedia](https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Piaget's_theory_of_cognitive_development).
## Overview
This overview is a mixed of both ideas from the book altogether with other
......@@ -33,6 +37,90 @@ not composed of intelligence alone. Other instances exist that might put the
whole apparatus on restricted modes of operation, such when in a neurosis which
is a state of constant looping in a given theme.
## Misc
* Perception (imediate contact with the world) (127).
* Habit: beyond short and rapidly automatised connections between per-
ceptions and responses (habit) (127).
## Intelligence and equilibrium
Then, if intelligence is thus conceived as the form of equilibrium towards
which all cognitive processes tend, there arises the problem of its relations
with perception (Chap. 3), and with habit (Chap. 4).
-- Preface
Every response, whether it be an act directed towards the outside world or an
act internalized as thought, takes the form of an adaptation or, better, of a
re-adaptation. The individual acts only if he experiences a need, i.e., if the
equilibrium between the environment and the organism is momentarily upset, and
action tends to re-establish the equilibrium, i.e., to re-adapt the organ- ism
(Claparède). A response is thus a particular case of inter- action between the
external world and the subject, but unlike physiological interactions, which
are of a material nature and involve an internal change in the bodies which are
present, the responses studied by psychology are of a functional nature and are
achieved at greater and greater distances in space (percep- tion, etc.) and in
time (memory, etc.) besides following more and more complex paths (reversals,
detours, etc.). Behaviour, thus conceived in terms of functional interaction,
presupposes two essential and closely interdependent aspects: an affective
aspect and a cognitive aspect.
-- 5
Furthermore, intelligence itself does not consist of an isolated and sharply
differentiated class of cognitive processes. It is not, properly speaking, one
form of structuring among others; it is the form of equilibrium towards which
all the structures arising out of perception, habit and elementary
sensori-motor mechan- isms tend. It must be understood that if intelligence is
not a faculty this denial involves a radical functional continuity between the
higher forms of thought and the whole mass of lower types of cognitive and
motor adaptation; so intelligence can only be the form of equilibrium towards
which these tend.
This does not mean, of course, that a judgment consists of a co- ordination of
perceptual structures, or that perceiving means unconscious inference (although
both these theories have been held), for functional continuity in no way
excludes diversity or even heterogeneity among structures. Every structure is
to be thought of as a particular form of equilibrium, more or less stable
within its restricted field and losing its stability on reach- ing the limits of
the field. But these structures, forming different levels, are to be regarded as
succeeding one another according to a law of development, such that each one
brings about a more inclusive and stable equilibrium for the processes that
emerge from the preceding level. Intelligence is thus only a generic term to
indicate the superior forms of organization or equilibrium of cognitive
structurings.
-- 7
In general, we may thus conclude that there is an essential unity between the
sensori-motor processes that engender per- ceptual activity, the formation of
habits, and pre-verbal or pre- representative intelligence itself. The latter
does not therefore arise as a new power, superimposed all of a sudden on com-
pletely prepared previous mechanisms, but is only the expres- sion of these
same mechanisms when they go beyond present and immediate contact with the
world (perception), as well as beyond short and rapidly automatised connections
between per- ceptions and responses (habit), and operate at progressively
greater distances and by more complex routes, in the direction of mobility and
reversibility. Early intelligence, therefore, is simply the form of mobile
equilibrium towards which the mechanisms adapted to perception and habit tend;
but the latter attain this only by leaving their respective fields of
application. Moreover, intelligence, from this first sensori-motor stage
onwards, has already succeeded in constructing, in the special case of space,
the equilibrated structure that we call the group of displacements—in an
entirely empirical or practical form, it is true, and of course remaining on
the very restricted plane of immediate space. But it goes without saying that
this organiza- tion, circumscribed as it is by the limitations of action, still
does not constitute a form of thought. On the contrary, the whole development
of thought, from the advent of language to the end of childhood, is necessary
in order that the completed sensori- motor structures, which may even be
co-ordinated in the form of empirical groups, may be extended into genuine
operations, which will constitute or reconstruct these groupings and groups at
the level of symbolic behaviour and reflective reasoning.
-- 127-128
## Logic and psychology
An axiomatics is an exclusively hypothetico-deductive sci-
......@@ -171,3 +259,68 @@ Innovation:
new possibilities.
-- 114
Topology:
But there now arises a problem whose discussion leads to the study of space.
Perceptual constancy is the product of simple regulations and we saw (Chap. 3)
that the absence at all ages of absolute constancy and the existence of adult
“superconstancy” provide evidence for the regulative rather than operational
char- acter of the system. There is, therefore, all the more reason why it
should be true of the first two years. Does not the construction of space, on
the other hand, lead quite rapidly to a grouping structure and even a group
structure in accordance with
Poincaré’s famous hypothesis concerning the psychologically primary influence of
the “group of displacements?” The genesis of space in sensori-motor
intelligence is com- pletely dominated by the progressive organisation of
responses, and this in effect leads to a “group” structure. But, contrary to
Poincaré’s belief in the a priori nature of the group of dis- placements, this
is developed gradually as the ultimate form of equilibrium reached by this
motor organisation. Successive co-ordinations (combinativity), reversals
(reversibility), detours (associativity) and conservations of position
(identity) gradually give rise to the group, which serves as a necessary
equilibrium for actions.
At the first two stages (reflexes and elementary habits), we could not even speak
of a space common to the various per- ceptual modalities, since there are as
many spaces, all mutually heterogeneous, as there are qualitatively distinct
fields (mouth, visual, tactile, etc.). It is only in the course of the third
stage that the mutual assimilation of these various spaces becomes system- atic
owing to the co-ordination of vision with prehension. Now, step by step with
these co-ordinations, we see growing up elementary spatial systems which
already presage the form of composition characteristic of the group. Thus, in
the case of interrupted circular reaction, the subject returns to the starting-
point to begin again; when his eyes are following a moving object that is
travelling too fast for continuous vision (falling etc.), the subject
occasionally catches up with the object by dis- placements of his own body to
correct for those of the external moving object.
But it is as well to realise that, if we take the point of view of the subject
and not merely that of a mathematical observer, the construction of a group
structure implies at least two conditions: the concept of an object and the
decentralisation of movements by correcting for, and even reversing, their
initial egocentricity. In fact, it is clear that the reversibility
characteristic of the group presupposes the concept of an object, and also vice
versa, since to retrieve an object is to make it possible for oneself to return
(by displacing either the object itself or one’s own body). The object is
simply the constant due to the reversible composition of the group.
Furthermore, as Poincaré himself has clearly shown, the idea of displacement as
such implies the possibility of differentiating between irreversible changes of
state and those changes of position that are characterized precisely by their
reversibility (or by their possible correction through movements of one’s own
body). It is obvious, therefore, that without con- servation of objects there
could not be any “group”, since then everything would appear as a “change of
state”. The object and the group of displacements are thus indissociable, the
one con- stituting the static aspect and the other the dynamic aspect of the
same reality. But this is not all: a world with no objects is a universe with
no systematic differentiation between subjective and external realities, a world
that is consequently “adualistic” (J. M. Baldwin). By this very fact, such a
universe would be centred on one’s own actions, the subject being all the more
dominated by this egocentric point of view because he remains
un-self-conscious. But the group implies just the opposite attitude: a complete
decentralisation, such that one’s own body is located as one element among
others in a system of displacements enabling one to distinguish between one’s
own movements and those of objects.
-- 123-125
0% Loading or .
You are about to add 0 people to the discussion. Proceed with caution.
Please register or to comment