Newer
Older
* Terms: institutionalized, adjusted sublimation
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
## Snippets
### Intro
From the beginning, any critical theory of society is thus confronted with the
problem of historical objectivity, a problem which arises at the two points
where the analysis implies value judgments:
1. the judgment that human life is worth living, or rather can be and ought to
be made worth living. This judgment underlies all intellectual effort; it is
the a priori of social theory, and its rejection (which is perfectly logical)
rejects theory itself;
2. the judgment that, in a given society, specific possibilities exist for the
amelioration of human life and specific ways and means of realizing these
possibilities. Critical analysis has to demonstrate the objective validity of
these judgments, and the demonstration has to proceed on empirical grounds. The
established society has available an ascertainable quantity and quality of
intellectual and material resources. How can these resources be used for the
optimal development and satisfaction of individual needs and faculties with a
minimum of toil and misery? Social theory is historical theory, and history is
the realm of chance in the realm of necessity. Therefore, among the various
possible and actual modes of organizing and utilizing the available resources,
which ones offer the greatest chance of an optimal development?
[...]
The “possibilities” must be within the reach of the respective society; they
must be definable goals of practice. By the same token, the abstraction from
the established institutions must be expressive of an actual tendency—that is,
their transformation must be the real need of the underlying population. Social
theory is concerned with the historical alternatives which haunt the
established society as subversive tendencies and forces. The values attached to
the alternatives do become facts when they are translated into reality by
historical practice. The theoretical concepts terminate with social change.
But here, advanced industrial society confronts the critique with a situation
which seems to deprive it of its very basis. Technical progress, extended to a
whole system of domination and coordination, creates forms of life (and of
power) which appear to reconcile the forces opposing the system and to defeat
or refute all protest in the name of the historical prospects of freedom from
toil and domination. Contemporary society seems to be capable of containing
social change—qualitative change which would establish essentially different
institutions, a new direction of the productive process, new modes of human
existence.
[...]
As a technological universe, advanced industrial society is a political
universe, the latest stage in the realization of a specific historical
project—namely, the experience, transformation, and organization of nature as
the mere stuff of domination.
As the project unfolds, it shapes the entire universe of discourse and action,
intellectual and material culture. In the medium of technology, culture,
politics, and the economy merge into an omnipresent system which swallows up or
repulses all alternatives. The productivity and growth potential of this system
stabilize the society and contain technical progress within the framework of
domination. Technological rationality has become political rationality.
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
### Freedom in negative terms
Contemporary industrial civilization demonstrates that it has reached the stage
at which “the free society” can no longer be adequately defined in the
traditional terms of economic, political, and intellectual liberties, not
because these liberties have become insignificant, but because they are too
significant to be confined within the traditional forms. New modes of
realization are needed, corresponding to the new capabilities of society.
Such new modes can be indicated only in negative terms because they would
amount to the negation of the prevailing modes. Thus economic freedom would
mean freedom from the economy—from being controlled by economic forces and
relationships; freedom from the daily struggle for existence, from earning a
living. Political freedom would mean liberation of the individuals from
politics over which they have no effective control. Similarly, intellectual
freedom would mean the restoration of individual thought now absorbed by mass
communication and indoctrination, abolition of “public opinion” together with
its makers. The unrealistic sound of these propositions is indicative, not of
their utopian character, but of the strength of the forces which prevent their
realization. The most effective and enduring form of warfare against liberation
is the implanting of material and intellectual needs that perpetuate obsolete
forms of the struggle for existence.
The intensity, the satisfaction and even the character of human needs, beyond
the biological level, have always been preconditioned. Whether or not the
possibility of doing or leaving, enjoying or destroying, possessing or
rejecting something is seized as a need depends on whether or not it can be
seen as desirable and necessary for the prevailing societal institutions and
interests. In this sense, human needs are historical needs and, to the extent
to which the society demands the repressive development of the individual, his
needs themselves and their claim for satisfaction are subject to overriding
critical standards.
### The irrationality of the rational
We are again confronted with one of the most vexing aspects of advanced
industrial civilization: the rational character of its irrationality. Its
productivity and efficiency, its capacity to increase and spread comforts, to
turn waste into need, and destruction into construction, the extent to which
this civilization transforms the object world into an extension of man’s mind
and body makes the very notion of alienation questionable.
[...]
But in the contemporary period, the technological controls appear to be the
very embodiment of Reason for the benefit of all social groups and interests—to
such an extent that all contradiction seems irrational and all counteraction
impossible.
No wonder then that, in the most advanced areas of this civilization, the
social controls have been introjected to the point where even individual
protest is affected at its roots. The intellectual and emotional refusal “to go
along” appears neurotic and impotent.
[...]
But the term “introjection” perhaps no longer describes the way in which the
individual by himself reproduces and perpetuates the external controls
exercised by his society. Introjection suggests a variety of relatively
spontaneous processes by which a Self (Ego) transposes the “outer” into the
“inner.” Thus introjection implies the existence of an inner dimension
distinguished from and even antagonistic to the external exigencies—an
individual consciousness and an individual unconscious apart from public
opinion and behavior.3 The idea of “inner freedom” here has its reality: it
designates the private space in which man may become and remain “himself.”
Today this private space has been invaded and whittled down by technological
reality. Mass production and mass distribution claim the entire individual, and
industrial psychology has long since ceased to be confined to the factory. The
manifold processes of introjection seem to be ossified in almost mechanical
reactions. The result is, not adjustment but mimesis: an immediate
identification of the individual with his society and, through it, with the
society as a whole.
### One-dimensionality
Thus emerges a pattern of one-dimensional thought and behavior in which ideas,
aspirations, and objectives that, by their content, transcend the established
universe of discourse and action are either repelled or reduced to terms of
this universe. They are redefined by the rationality of the given system and of
its quantitative extension.
The trend may be related to a development in scientific method: operationalism
in the physical, behaviorism in the social sciences. The common feature is a
total empiricism in the treatment of concepts; their meaning is restricted to
the representation of particular operations and behavior. The operational point
of view is well illustrated by P. W. Bridgman’s analysis of the concept of
length:5
We evidently know what we mean by length if we can tell what the length of any
and every object is, and for the physicist nothing more is required. To find
the length of an object, we have to perform certain physical operations. The
concept of length is therefore fixed when the operations by which length is
measured are fixed: that is, the concept of length involves as much and nothing
more than the set of operations by which length is determined. In general, we
mean by any concept nothing more than a set of operations; the concept is
synonymous with the corresponding set of operations.
Bridgman has seen the wide implications of this mode of thought for the society
at large:6
To adopt the operational point of view involves much more than a mere
restriction of the sense in which we understand ‘concept,’ but means a
far-reaching change in all our habits of thought, in that we shall no longer
permit ourselves to use as tools in our thinking concepts of which we cannot
give an adequate account in terms of operations.
Bridgman’s prediction has come true. The new mode of thought is today the
predominant tendency in philosophy, psychology, sociology, and other fields.
Many of the most seriously troublesome concepts are being “eliminated” by
showing that no adequate account of them in terms of operations or behavior can
be given.
[...]
Outside the academic establishment, the “far-reaching change in all our habits
of thought” is more serious. It serves to coordinate ideas and goals with those
exacted by the prevailing system, to enclose them in the system, and to repel
those which are irreconcilable with the system. The reign of such a
one-dimensional reality does not mean that materialism rules, and that the
spiritual, metaphysical, and bohemian occupations are petering out. On the
contrary, there is a great deal of “Worship together this week,” “Why not try
God,” Zen, existentialism, and beat ways of life, etc. But such modes of
protest and transcendence are no longer contradictory to the status quo and no
longer negative. They are rather the ceremonial part of practical behaviorism,
its harmless negation, and are quickly digested by the status quo as part of
its healthy diet.
[...]
Such limitation of thought is certainly not new. Ascending modern rationalism,
in its speculative as well as empirical form, shows a striking contrast between
extreme critical radicalism in scientific and philosophic method on the one
hand, and an uncritical quietism in the attitude toward established and
functioning social institutions. Thus Descartes’ ego cogitans was to leave the
“great public bodies” untouched, and Hobbes held that “the present ought always
to be preferred, maintained, and accounted best.” Kant agreed with Locke in
justifying revolution if and when it has succeeded in organizing the whole and
in preventing subversion.
### Progress, abolition of labor, totalitarianism
The society bars a whole type of oppositional operations and behavior;
consequently, the concepts pertaining to them are rendered illusory or
meaningless. Historical transcendence appears as metaphysical transcendence,
not acceptable to science and scientific thought. The operational and
behavioral point of view, practiced as a “habit of thought” at large, becomes
the view of the established universe of discourse and action, needs and
aspirations.
“Progress” is not a neutral term; it moves toward specific ends, and these ends
are defined by the possibilities of ameliorating the human condition. Advanced
industrial society is approaching the stage where continued progress would
demand the radical subversion of the prevailing direction and organization of
progress. This stage would be reached when material production (including the
necessary services) becomes automated to the extent that all vital needs can be
satisfied while necessary labor time is reduced to marginal time. From this
point on, technical progress would transcend the realm of necessity, where it
served as the instrument of domination and exploitation which thereby limited
its rationality; technology would become subject to the free play of faculties
in the struggle for the pacification of nature and of society.
Such a state is envisioned in Marx’s notion of the “abolition of labor.” The
term “pacification of existence” seems better suited to designate the
historical alternative of a world which—through an international conflict which
transforms and suspends the contradictions within the established
societies—advances on the brink of a global war. “Pacification of existence”
means the development of man’s struggle with man and with nature, under
conditions where the competing needs, desires, and aspirations are no longer
organized by vested interests in domination and scarcity—an organization which
perpetuates the destructive forms of this struggle.
Today’s fight against this historical alternative finds a firm mass basis in
the underlying population, and finds its ideology in the rigid orientation of
thought and behavior to the given universe of facts. Validated by the
accomplishments of science and technology, justified by its growing
productivity, the status quo defies all transcendence. Faced with the
possibility of pacification on the grounds of its technical and intellectual
achievements, the mature industrial society closes itself against this
alternative. Operationalism, in theory and practice, becomes the theory and
practice of containment. Underneath its obvious dynamics, this society is a
thoroughly static system of life: self-propelling in its oppressive
productivity and in its beneficial coordination. Containment of technical
progress goes hand in hand with its growth in the established direction. In
spite of the political fetters imposed by the status quo, the more technology
appears capable of creating the conditions for pacification, the more are the
minds and bodies of man organized against this alternative.
The most advanced areas of industrial society exhibit throughout these two
features: a trend toward consummation of technological rationality, and
intensive efforts to contain this trend within the established institutions.
Here is the internal contradiction of this civilization: the irrational element
in its rationality. It is the token of its achievements. The industrial society
which makes technology and science its own is organized for the
ever-more-effective domination of man and nature, for the ever-more-effective
utilization of its resources. It becomes irrational when the success of these
efforts opens new dimensions of human realization. Organization for peace is
different from organization for war; the institutions which served the struggle
for existence cannot serve the pacification of existence. Life as an end is
qualitatively different from life as a means.
[...]
Qualitative change also involves a change in the technical basis on which this
society rests—one which sustains the economic and political institutions
through which the “second nature” of man as an aggressive object of
administration is stabilized.
[...]
To be sure, labor must precede the reduction of labor, and industrialization
must precede the development of human needs and satisfactions. But as all
freedom depends on the conquest of alien necessity, the realization of freedom
depends on the techniques of this conquest. The highest productivity of labor
can be used for the perpetuation of labor, and the most efficient
industrialization can serve the restriction and manipulation of needs.
When this point is reached, domination—in the guise of affluence and
liberty—extends to all spheres of private and public existence, integrates all
authentic opposition, absorbs all alternatives. Technological rationality
reveals its political character as it becomes the great vehicle of better
domination, creating a truly totalitarian universe in which society and nature,
mind and body are kept in a state of permanent mobilization for the defense of
this universe.
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
### Revolution
The classical Marxian theory envisages the transition from capitalism to
socialism as a political revolution: the proletariat destroys the political
apparatus of capitalism but retains the technological apparatus, subjecting it
to socialization. There is continuity in the revolution: technological
rationality, freed from irrational restrictions and destructions, sustains and
consummates itself in the new society. It is interesting to read a Soviet
Marxist statement on this continuity, which is of such vital importance for the
notion of socialism as the determinate negation of capitalism
[...]
To be sure, Marx held that organization and direction of the productive
apparatus by the “immediate producers” would introduce a qualitative change in
the technical continuity: namely, production toward the satisfaction of freely
developing individual needs. However, to the degree to which the established
technical apparatus engulfs the public and private existence in all spheres of
society—that is, becomes the medium of control and cohesion in a political
universe which incorporates the laboring classes—to that degree would the
qualitative change involve a change in the technological structure itself. And
such change would presuppose that the laboring classes are alienated from this
universe in their very existence, that their consciousness is that of the total
impossibility to continue to exist in this universe, so that the need for
qualitative change is a matter of life and death. Thus, the negation exists
prior to the change itself, the notion that the liberating historical forces
develop within the established society is a cornerstone of Marxian theory.2
### Hell
Those whose life is the hell of the Affluent Society are kept in line by a
brutality which revives medieval and early modern practices. For the other,
less underprivileged people, society takes care of the need for liberation by
satisfying the needs which make servitude palatable and perhaps even
unnoticeable, and it accomplishes this fact in the process of production
itself.
### Automation
(1) Mechanization is increasingly reducing the quantity and intensity of physical
energy expended in labor. This evolution is of great bearing on the Marxian
concept of the worker (proletarian). To Marx, the proletarian is primarily the
manual laborer who expends and exhausts his physical energy in the work
process, even if he works with machines. The purchase and use of this physical
energy, under subhuman conditions, for the private appropriation of
surplus-value entailed the revolting inhuman aspects of exploitation; the
Marxian notion denounces the physical pain and misery of labor. This is the
material, tangible element in wage slavery and alienation—the physiological and
biological dimension of classical capitalism.
“Pendant les siècles passés, une cause importante d’aliénation résidait dans le
fait que l’être humain prêtait son individualité biologique à l’organisation
technique: il était porteur d’outils; les ensembles techniques ne pouvaient se
constituer qu’en incorporant l’homme comme porteur d’outils. Le caractère
déformant de la profession était à la fois psychique et somatique.”3
3. “During the past centuries, one important reason for alienation was that the
human being lent his biological individuality to the technical apparatus: he
was the bearer of tools; technical units could not be established without
incorporating man as bearer of tools into them. The nature of this occupation
was such that it was both psychologically and physiologically deforming in its
effect.” Gilbert Simondon, Du Mode d’existence des objets techniques (Paris:
Aubier, 1958), p. 103, note.
Now the ever-more-complete mechanization of labor in advanced capitalism, while
sustaining exploitation, modifies the attitude and the status of the exploited.
Within the technological ensemble, mechanized work in which automatic and
semi-automatic reactions fill the larger part (if not the whole) of labor time
remains, as a life-long occupation, exhausting, stupefying, inhuman
slavery—even more exhausting because of increased speed-up, control of the
machine operators (rather than of the product), and isolation of the workers
from each other.4 To be sure, this form of drudgery is expressive of arrested,
partial automation, of the coexistence of automated, semi-automated, and
non-automated sections within the same plant, but even under these conditions,
“for muscular fatigue technology has substituted tension and/or mental
effort.”5 For the more advanced automated plants, the transformation of
physical energy into technical and mental skills is emphasized:
“… skills of the head rather than of the hand, of the logician rather than the
craftsman; of nerve rather than muscle; of the pilot rather than the manual
worker; of the maintenance man rather than the operator.”6
This kind of masterly enslavement is not essentially different from that of the
typist, the bank teller, the high-pressure salesman or saleswoman, and the
television announcer. Standardization and the routine assimilate productive and
non-productive jobs. The proletarian of the previous stages of capitalism was
indeed the beast of burden, by the labor of his body procuring the necessities
and luxuries of life while living in filth and poverty. Thus he was the living
denial of his society.7 In contrast, the organized worker in the advanced areas
of the technological society lives this denial less conspicuously and, like the
other human objects of the social division of labor, he is being incorporated
into the technological community of the administered population. Moreover, in
the most successful areas of automation, some sort of technological community
seems to integrate the human atoms at work. The machine seems to instill some
drugging rhythm in the operators:
“It is generally agreed that interdependent motions performed by a group of
persons which follow a rhythmic pattern yield satisfaction—quite apart from
what is being accomplished by the motions”;8 and the sociologist-observer
believes this to be a reason for the gradual development of a “general climate”
more “favorable both to production and to certain important kinds of human
satisfaction.” He speaks of the “growth of a strong in-group feeling in each
crew” and quotes one worker as stating: “All in all we are in the swing of
things …”9
The phrase admirably expresses the change in mechanized enslavement:
things swing rather than oppress, and they swing the human instrument—not only
its body but also its mind and even its soul. A remark by Sartre elucidates the
depth of the process:
“Aux premiers temps des machines semi-automatiques, des enquêtes ont montré que
les ouvrières spécialisées se laissaient aller, en travaillant, à une rêverie
d’ordre sexuel, elles se rappellaient la chambre, le lit, la nuit, tout ce qui
ne concerne que la personne dans la solitude du couple fermé sur soi. Mais
c’est la machine en elle qui rêvait de caresses.…”10 The machine process in the
technological universe breaks the innermost privacy of freedom and joins
sexuality and labor in one unconscious, rhythmic automatism—a process which
parallels the assimilation of jobs.10
10. “Shortly after semi-automatic machines were introduced, investigations
showed that female skilled workers would allow themselves to lapse while
working into a sexual kind of daydream; they would recall the bedroom, the bed,
the night and all that concerns only the person within the solitude of the
couple alone with itself. But it was the machine in her which was dreaming of
caresses …” Jean-Paul Sartre, Critique de la raison dialectique, tome I (Paris:
Gallimard, 1960), p. 290.
The machine process in the technological universe breaks the innermost privacy
of freedom and joins sexuality and labor in one unconscious, rhythmic
automatism—a process which parallels the assimilation of jobs.
[...]
(2) The assimilating trend shows forth in the occupational stratification. In
the key industrial establishments, the “blue-collar” work force declines in
relation to the “white-collar” element; the number of non-production workers
increases.11 This quantitative change refers back to a change in the character
of the basic instruments of production.12 At the advanced stage of
mechanization, as part of the technological reality, the machine is not
“une unité absolue, mais seulement une réalité technique individualisée,
ouverte selon deux voies: celle de la relation aux éléments, et celle des
relations interindividuelles dans l’ensemble technique.”13
13. “an absolute unity, but only an individualized technical reality open in
two directions, that of the relation to the elements and that of the relation
among the individuals in the technical whole.” Gilbert Simondon, loc. cit., p.
146.
[...]
To the extent to which the machine becomes itself a system of mechanical tools
and relations and thus extends far beyond the individual work process, it
asserts its larger dominion by reducing the “professional autonomy” of the
laborer and integrating him with other professions which suffer and direct the
technical ensemble. To be sure, the former “professional” autonomy of the
laborer was rather his professional enslavement. But this specific mode of
enslavement was at the same time the source of his specific, professional power
of negation—the power to stop a process which threatened him with annihilation
as a human being. Now the laborer is losing the professional autonomy which
made him a member of a class set off from the other occupational groups because
it embodied the refutation of the established society.
The technological change which tends to do away with the machine as individual
instrument of production, as “absolute unit,” seems to cancel the Marxian
notion of the “organic composition of capital” and with it the theory of the
creation of surplus value. According to Marx, the machine never creates value
but merely transfers its own value to the product, while surplus value remains
the result of the exploitation of living labor. The machine is embodiment of
human labor power, and through it, past labor (dead labor) preserves itself and
determines living labor. Now automation seems to alter qualitatively the
relation between dead and living labor; it tends toward the point where
productivity is determined “by the machines, and not by the individual
output.”14 Moreover, the very measurement of individual output becomes
impossible:
“Automation in its largest sense means, in effect, the end of measurement of
work.… With automation, you can’t measure output of a single man; you now have
to measure simply equipment utilization. If that is generalized as a kind of
concept … there is no longer, for example, any reason at all to pay a man by
the piece or pay him by the hour,” that is to say, there is no more reason to
keep up the “dual pay system” of salaries and wages.”15
Daniel Bell, the author of this report, goes further; he links this
technological change to the historical system of industrialization itself: the
meaning of industrialization did not arise with the introduction of factories,
it “arose out of the measurement of work. It’s when work can be measured, when
you can hitch a man to the job, when you can put a harness on him, and measure
his output in terms of a single piece and pay him by the piece or by the hour,
that you have got modern industrialization.”16
### Servitude
(4) The new technological work-world thus enforces a weakening of the negative
position of the working class: the latter no longer appears to be the living
contradiction to the established society. This trend is strengthened by the
effect of the technological organization of production on the other side of the
fence: on management and direction. Domination is transfigured into
administration.21 The capitalist bosses and owners are losing their identity as
responsible agents; they are assuming the function of bureaucrats in a
corporate machine. Within the vast hierarchy of executive and managerial boards
extending far beyond the individual establishment into the scientific
laboratory and research institute, the national government and national
purpose, the tangible source of exploitation disappears behind the façade of
objective rationality. Hatred and frustration are deprived of their specific
target, and the technological veil conceals the reproduction of inequality and
enslavement.22 With technical progress as its instrument, unfreedom—in the
sense of man’s subjection to his productive apparatus—is perpetuated and
intensified in the form of many liberties and comforts. The novel feature is
the overwhelming rationality in this irrational enterprise, and the depth of
the preconditioning which shapes the instinctual drives and aspirations of the
individuals and obscures the difference between false and true consciousness.
For in reality, neither the utilization of administrative rather than physical
controls (hunger, personal dependence, force), nor the change in the character
of heavy work, nor the assimilation of occupational classes, nor the
equalization in the sphere of consumption compensate for the fact that the
decisions over life and death, over personal and national security are made at
places over which the individuals have no control. The slaves of developed
industrial civilization are sublimated slaves, but they are slaves, for slavery
is determined
“pas par l’obéissance, ni par la rudesse des labeurs, mais par le statu
d’instrument et la réduction de l’homme à l’état de chose.”23
23. “neither by obedience nor by hardness of labor but by the status of being a
mere instrument, and the reduction of man to the state of a thing.” François
Perroux, La Coexistence pacifique, (Paris, Presses Universitaires, 1958), vol.
III, p. 600.
This is the pure form of servitude: to exist as an instrument, as a thing. And
this mode of existence is not abrogated if the thing is animated and chooses
its material and intellectual food, if it does not feel its being-a-thing, if
it is a pretty, clean, mobile thing. Conversely, as reification tends to become
totalitarian by virtue of its technological form, the organizers and
administrators themselves become increasingly dependent on the machinery which
they organize and administer. And this mutual dependence is no longer the
dialectical relationship between Master and Servant, which has been broken in
the struggle for mutual recognition, but rather a vicious circle which encloses
both the Master and the Servant. Do the technicians rule, or is their rule that
of the others, who rely on the technicians as their planners and executors?
[...]
A vicious circle seems indeed the proper image of a society which is
self-expanding and self-perpetuating in its own preestablished direction—driven
by the growing needs which it generates and, at the same time, contains.
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
### Culture
The greatness of a free literature and art, the ideals of humanism, the sorrows
and joys of the individual, the fulfillment of the personality are important
items in the competitive struggle between East and West. They speak heavily
against the present forms of communism, and they are daily administered and
sold. The fact that they contradict the society which sells them does not
count. Just as people know or feel that advertisements and political platforms
must not be necessarily true or right, and yet hear and read them and even let
themselves be guided by them, so they accept the traditional values and make
them part of their mental equipment. If mass communications blend together
harmoniously, and often unnoticeably, art, politics, religion, and philosophy
with commercials, they bring these realms of culture to their common
denominator—the commodity form. The music of the soul is also the music of
salesmanship. Exchange value, not truth value counts. On it centers the
rationality of the status quo, and all alien rationality is bent to it.
As the great words of freedom and fulfillment are pronounced by campaigning
leaders and politicians, on the screens and radios and stages, they turn into
meaningless sounds which obtain meaning only in the context of propaganda,
business, discipline, and relaxation. This assimilation of the ideal with
reality testifies to the extent to which the ideal has been surpassed. It is
brought down from the sublimated realm of the soul or the spirit or the inner
man, and translated into operational terms and problems. Here are the
progressive elements of mass culture. The perversion is indicative of the fact
that advanced industrial society is confronted with the possibility of a
materialization of ideals. The capabilities of this society are progressively
reducing the sublimated realm in which the condition of man was represented,
idealized, and indicted. Higher culture becomes part of the material culture.
In this transformation, it loses the greater part of its truth.
[...]
Domination has its own aesthetics, and democratic domination has its democratic
aesthetics. It is good that almost everyone can now have the fine arts at his
fingertips, by just turning a knob on his set, or by just stepping into his
drugstore. In this diffusion, however, they become cogs in a culture-machine
which remakes their content.
[...]
Obviously, the physical transformation of the world entails the mental
transformation of its symbols, images, and ideas. Obviously, when cities and
highways and National Parks replace the villages, valleys, and forests; when
motorboats race over the lakes and planes cut through the skies—then these
areas lose their character as a qualitatively different reality, as areas of
contradiction.
And since contradiction is the work of the Logos—rational confrontation of
“that which is not” with “that which is”—it must have a medium of
communication. The struggle for this medium, or rather the struggle against its
absorption into the predominant one-dimensionality, shows forth in the
avant-garde efforts to create an estrangement which would make the artistic
truth again communicable.
Bertolt Brecht has sketched the theoretical foundations for these efforts. The
total character of the established society confronts the playwright with the
question of whether it is still possible to “represent the contemporary world
in the theater”—that is, represent it in such a manner that the spectator
recognizes the truth which the play is to convey. Brecht answers that the
contemporary world can be thus represented only if it is represented as subject
to change3—as the state of negativity which is to be negated. This is doctrine
which has to be learned, comprehended, and acted upon; but the theater is and
ought to be entertainment, pleasure. However, entertainment and learning are
not opposites; entertainment may be the most effective mode of learning. To
teach what the contemporary world really is behind the ideological and material
veil, and how it can be changed, the theater must break the spectator’s
identification with the events on the stage.
Not empathy and feeling, but distance and reflection are required. The
“estrangement-effect” (Verfremdungseffekt) is to produce this dissociation in
which the world can be recognized as what it is. “The things of everyday life
are lifted out of the realm of the self-evident.…”4 “That which is ‘natural’
must assume the features of the extraordinary. Only in this manner can the laws
of cause and effect reveal themselves.”5
[...]
The efforts to recapture the Great Refusal in the language of literature suffer
the fate of being absorbed by what they refute. As modern classics, the
avant-garde and the beatniks share in the function of entertaining without
endangering the good conscience of the men of good will. This absorption is
justified by technical progress; the refusal is refuted by the alleviation of
misery in the advanced industrial society. The liquidation of high culture is a
byproduct of the conquest of nature, and of the progressing conquest of
scarcity.
Invalidating the cherished images of transcendence by incorporating them into
its omnipresent daily reality, this society testifies to the extent to which
insoluble conflicts are becoming manageable—to which tragedy and romance,
archetypal dreams and anxieties are being made susceptible to technical
solution and dissolution. The psychiatrist takes care of the Don Juans, Romeos,
Hamlets, Fausts, as he takes care of Oedipus—he cures them. The rulers of the
world are losing their metaphysical features. Their appearance on television,
at press conferences, in parliament, and at public hearings is hardly suitable
for drama beyond that of the advertisement,14 while the consequences of their
actions surpass the scope of the drama.
### Adjusted desublimation
In contrast to the pleasures of adjusted desublimation, sublimation preserves
the consciousness of the renunciations which the repressive society inflicts
upon the individual, and thereby preserves the need for liberation. To be sure,
all sublimation is enforced by the power of society, but the unhappy
consciousness of this power already breaks through alienation. To be sure, all
sublimation accepts the social barrier to instinctual gratification, but it
also transgresses this barrier.
The Superego, in censoring the unconscious and in implanting conscience, also
censors the censor because the developed conscience registers the forbidden
evil act not only in the individual but also in his society. Conversely, loss
of conscience due to the satisfactory liberties granted by an unfree society
makes for a happy consciousness which facilitates acceptance of the misdeeds of
this society. It is the token of declining autonomy and comprehension.
Sublimation demands a high degree of autonomy and comprehension; it is
mediation between the conscious and the unconscious, between the primary and
secondary processes, between the intellect and instinct, renunciation and
rebellion. In its most accomplished modes, such as in the artistic oeuvre,
sublimation becomes the cognitive power which defeats suppression while bowing
to it.
In the light of the cognitive function of this mode of sublimation, the
desublimation rampant in advanced industrial society reveals its truly
conformist function. This liberation of sexuality (and of aggressiveness) frees
the instinctual drives from much of the unhappiness and discontent that
elucidate the repressive power of the established universe of satisfaction. To
be sure, there is pervasive unhappiness, and the happy consciousness is shaky
enough—a thin surface over fear, frustration, and disgust. This unhappiness
lends itself easily to political mobilization; without room for conscious
development, it may become the instinctual reservoir for a new fascist way of
life and death. But there are many ways in which the unhappiness beneath the
happy consciousness may be turned into a source of strength and cohesion for
the social order. The conflicts of the unhappy individual now seem far more
amenable to cure than those which made for Freud’s “discontent in
civilization,” and they seem more adequately defined in terms of the “neurotic
personality of our time” than in terms of the eternal struggle between Eros and
Thanatos.
[...]
In accordance with the terminology used in the later works of Freud: sexuality
as “specialized” partial drive; Eros as that of the entire organism.
### Crust
In this general necessity, guilt has no place. One man can give the signal that
liquidates hundreds and thousands of people, then declare himself free from all
pangs of conscience, and live happily ever after. The antifascist powers who
beat fascism on the battlefields reap the benefits of the Nazi scientists,
generals, and engineers; they have the historical advantage of the late-comer.
What begins as the horror of the concentration camps turns into the practice of
training people for abnormal conditions—a subterranean human existence and the
daily intake of radioactive nourishment. A Christian minister declares that it
does not contradict Christian principles to prevent with all available means
your neighbor from entering your bomb shelter. Another Christian minister
contradicts his colleague and says it does. Who is right? Again, the neutrality
of technological rationality shows forth over and above politics, and again it
shows forth as spurious, for in both cases, it serves the politics of
domination.
[...]
It seems that even the most hideous transgressions can be repressed in such a
manner that, for all practical purposes, they have ceased to be a danger for
society. Or, if their eruption leads to functional disturbances in the
individual (as in the case of one Hiroshima pilot), it does not disturb the
functioning of society. A mental hospital manages the disturbance.
### Game
The Happy Consciousness has no limits—it arranges games with death and
disfiguration in which fun, team work, and strategic importance mix in
rewarding social harmony. The Rand Corporation, which unites scholarship,
research, the military, the climate, and the good life, reports such games in a
style of absolving cuteness, in its “RANDom News,” volume 9, number 1, under
the heading BETTER SAFE THAN SORRY. The rockets are rattling, the H-bomb is
waiting, and the space-flights are flying, and the problem is “how to guard the
nation and the free world.” In all this, the military planners are worried, for
“the cost of taking chances, of experimenting and making a mistake, may be
fearfully high.” But here RAND comes in; RAND relieves, and “devices like
RAND’S SAFE come into the picture.” The picture into which they come is
unclassified. It is a picture in which “the world becomes a map, missiles
merely symbols [long live the soothing power of symbolism!], and wars just
[just] plans and calculations written down on paper …” In this picture, RAND
has transfigured the world into an interesting technological game, and one can
relax—the “military planners can gain valuable ‘synthetic’ experience without
risk.”
PLAYING THE GAME
To understand the game one should participate, for understanding is “in the
experience.”
Because SAFE players have come from almost every department at RAND as well as
the Air Force, we might find a physicist, an engineer, and an economist on the
Blue team. The Red team will represent a similar cross-section.
The first day is taken up by a joint briefing on what the game is all about and
a study of the rules. When the teams are finally seated around the maps in
their respective rooms the game begins. Each team receives its policy statement
from the Game Director. These statements, usually prepared by a member of the
Control Group, give an estimate of the world situation at the time of playing,
some information on the policy of the opposing team, the objectives to be met
by the team, and the team’s budget. (The policies are changed for each game to
explore a wide range of strategic possibilities.)
### Guilt
Obviously, in the realm of the Happy Consciousness, guilt feeling has no place,
and the calculus takes care of conscience. When the whole is at stake, there is
no crime except that of rejecting the whole, or not defending it. Crime, guilt,
and guilt feeling become a private affair. Freud revealed in the psyche of the
individual the crimes of mankind, in the individual case history the history of
the whole. This fatal link is successfully suppressed. Those who identify
themselves with the whole, who are installed as the leaders and defenders of
the whole can make mistakes, but they cannot do wrong—they are not guilty. They
may become guilty again when this identification no longer holds, when they are
gone.
### The Happy Conciousness
The Happy Consciousness—the belief that the real is rational and that the
system delivers the goods—reflects the new conformism which is a facet of
technological rationality translated into social behavior.
### Language, memory and history
The unified, functional language is an irreconcilably anti-critical and
anti-dialectical language. In it, operational and behavioral rationality
absorbs the transcendent, negative, oppositional elements of Reason.
I shall discuss17 these elements in terms of the tension between the “is” and
the “ought,” between essence and appearance, potentiality and
actuality—ingression of the negative in the positive determinations of logic.
This sustained tension permeates the two-dimensional universe of discourse
which is the universe of critical, abstract thought. The two dimensions are
antagonistic to each other; the reality partakes of both of them, and the
dialectical concepts develop the real contradictions. In its own development,
dialectical thought came to comprehend the historical character of the
contradictions and the process of their mediation as historical process. Thus
the “other” dimension of thought appeared to be historical dimension—the
potentiality as historical possibility, its realization as historical event.
The suppresssion of this dimension in the societal universe of operational
rationality is a suppression of history, and this is not an academic but a
political affair. It is suppression of the society’s own past—and of its
future, inasmuch as this future invokes the qualitative change, the negation of
the present. A universe of discourse in which the categories of freedom
have become interchangeable and even identical with their opposites is not only
practicing Orwellian or Aesopian language but is repulsing and forgetting the
historical reality—the horror of fascism; the idea of socialism; the
preconditions of democracy; the content of freedom. If a bureaucratic
dictatorship rules and defines communist society, if fascist regimes are
functioning as partners of the Free World, if the welfare program of
enlightened capitalism is successfully defeated by labeling it “socialism,” if
the foundations of democracy are harmoniously abrogated in democracy, then the
old historical concepts are invalidated by up-to-date operational
redefinitions. The redefinitions are falsifications which, imposed by the
powers that be and the powers of fact, serve to transform falsehood into truth.
The functional language is a radically anti-historical language: operational
rationality has little room and little use for historical reason.18 Is this
fight against history part of the fight against a dimension of the mind in
which centrifugal faculties and forces might develop—faculties and forces that
might hinder the total coordination of the individual with the society?
Remembrance of the past may give rise to dangerous insights, and the
established society seems to be apprehensive of the subversive contents of
memory. Remembrance is a mode of dissociation from the given facts, a mode of
“mediation” which breaks, for short moments, the omnipresent power of the given
facts. Memory recalls the terror and the hope that passed. Both come to life
again, but whereas in reality, the former recurs in ever new forms, the latter
remains hope. And in the personal events which reappear in the individual
memory, the fears and aspirations of mankind assert themselves—the universal in
the particular. It is history which memory preserves. It succumbs to the
totalitarian power of the behavioral universe
[...]
The closed language does not demonstrate and explain—it communicates decision,
dictum, command. Where it defines, the definition becomes “separation of good
from evil”; it establishes unquestionable rights and wrongs, and one value as
justification of another value. It moves in tautologies, but the tautologies
are terribly effective “sentences.” They pass judgment in a “prejudged form”;
they pronounce condemnation. For example, the “objective content,” that is, the
definition of such terms as “deviationist,” “revisionist,” is that of the penal
code, and this sort of validation promotes a consciousness for which the
language of the powers that be is the language of truth.24
[...]
As the substance of the various regimes no longer appears in alternative modes
of life, it comes to rest in alternative techniques of manipulation and
control. Language not only reflects these controls but becomes itself an
instrument of control even where it does not transmit orders but information;
where it demands, not obedience but choice, not submission but freedom.